友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!
fundamental principles of the metaphysic of morals-第7部分
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部! 如果本书没有阅读完,想下次继续接着阅读,可使用上方 "收藏到我的浏览器" 功能 和 "加入书签" 功能!
will; then the actions of such a being which are recognised as
objectively necessary are subjectively necessary also; i。e。; the
will is a faculty to choose that only which reason independent of
inclination recognises as practically necessary; i。e。; as good。 But if
reason of itself does not sufficiently determine the will; if the
latter is subject also to subjective conditions (particular
impulses) which do not always coincide with the objective
conditions; in a word; if the will does not in itself completely
accord with reason (which is actually the case with men); then the
actions which objectively are recognised as necessary are subjectively
contingent; and the determination of such a will according to
objective laws is obligation; that is to say; the relation of the
objective laws to a will that is not thoroughly good is conceived as
the determination of the will of a rational being by principles of
reason; but which the will from its nature does not of necessity
follow。
The conception of an objective principle; in so far as it is
obligatory for a will; is called a command (of reason); and the
formula of the command is called an imperative。
All imperatives are expressed by the word ought 'or shall'; and
thereby indicate the relation of an objective law of reason to a will;
which from its subjective constitution is not necessarily determined
by it (an obligation)。 They say that something would be good to do
or to forbear; but they say it to a will which does not always do a
thing because it is conceived to be good to do it。 That is practically
good; however; which determines the will by means of the conceptions
of reason; and consequently not from subjective causes; but
objectively; that is on principles which are valid for every
rational being as such。 It is distinguished from the pleasant; as that
which influences the will only by means of sensation from merely
subjective causes; valid only for the sense of this or that one; and
not as a principle of reason; which holds for every one。*
*The dependence of the desires on sensations is called
inclination; and this accordingly always indicates a want。 The
dependence of a contingently determinable will on principles of reason
is called an interest。 This therefore; is found only in the case of
a dependent will which does not always of itself conform to reason; in
the Divine will we cannot conceive any interest。 But the human will
can also take an interest in a thing without therefore acting from
interest。 The former signifies the practical interest in the action;
the latter the pathological in the object of the action。 The former
indicates only dependence of the will on principles of reason in
themselves; the second; dependence on principles of reason for the
sake of inclination; reason supplying only the practical rules how the
requirement of the inclination may be satisfied。 In the first case the
action interests me; in the second the object of the action (because
it is pleasant to me)。 We have seen in the first section that in an
action done from duty we must look not to the interest in the
object; but only to that in the action itself; and in its rational
principle (viz。; the law)。
A perfectly good will would therefore be equally subject to
objective laws (viz。; laws of good); but could not be conceived as
obliged thereby to act lawfully; because of itself from its subjective
constitution it can only be determined by the conception of good。
Therefore no imperatives hold for the Divine will; or in general for a
holy will; ought is here out of place; because the volition is already
of itself necessarily in unison with the law。 Therefore imperatives
are only formulae to express the relation of objective laws of all
volition to the subjective imperfection of the will of this or that
rational being; e。g。; the human will。
Now all imperatives command either hypothetically or
categorically。 The former represent the practical necessity of a
possible action as means to something else that is willed (or at least
which one might possibly will)。 The categorical imperative would be
that which represented an action as necessary of itself without
reference to another end; i。e。; as objectively necessary。
Since every practical law represents a possible action as good
and; on this account; for a subject who is practically determinable by
reason; necessary; all imperatives are formulae determining an
action which is necessary according to the principle of a will good in
some respects。 If now the action is good only as a means to
something else; then the imperative is hypothetical; if it is
conceived as good in itself and consequently as being necessarily
the principle of a will which of itself conforms to reason; then it is
categorical。
Thus the imperative declares what action possible by me would be
good and presents the practical rule in relation to a will which
does not forthwith perform an action simply because it is good;
whether because the subject does not always know that it is good; or
because; even if it know this; yet its maxims might be opposed to
the objective principles of practical reason。
Accordingly the hypothetical imperative only says that the action is
good for some purpose; possible or actual。 In the first case it is a
problematical; in the second an assertorial practical principle。 The
categorical imperative which declares an action to be objectively
necessary in itself without reference to any purpose; i。e。; without
any other end; is valid as an apodeictic (practical) principle。
Whatever is possible only by the power of some rational being may
also be conceived as a possible purpose of some will; and therefore
the principles of action as regards the means necessary to attain some
possible purpose are in fact infinitely numerous。 All sciences have
a practical part; consisting of problems expressing that some end is
possible for us and of imperatives directing how it may be attained。
These may; therefore; be called in general imperatives of skill。
Here there is no question whether the end is rational and good; but
only what one must do in order to attain it。 The precepts for the
physician to make his patient thoroughly healthy; and for a poisoner
to ensure certain death; are of equal value in this respect; that each
serves to effect its purpose perfectly。 Since in early youth it cannot
be known what ends are likely to occur to us in the course of life;
parents seek to have their children taught a great many things; and
provide for their skill in the use of means for all sorts of arbitrary
ends; of none of which can they determine whether it may not perhaps
hereafter be an object to their pupil; but which it is at all events
possible that he might aim at; and this anxiety is so great that
they commonly neglect to form and correct their judgement on the value
of the things which may be chosen as ends。
There is one end; however; which may be assumed to be actually
such to all rational beings (so far as imperatives apply to them;
viz。; as dependent beings); and; therefore; one purpose which they not
merely may have; but which we may with certainty assume that they
all actually have by a natural necessity; and this is happiness。 The
hypothetical imperative which expresses the practical necessity of
an action as means to the advancement of happiness is assertorial。
We are not to present it as necessary for an uncertain and merely
possible purpose; but for a purpose which we may presuppose with
certainty and a priori in every man; because it belongs to his
being。 Now skill in the choice of means to his own greatest well…being
may be called prudence;* in the narrowest sense。 And thus the
imperative which refers to the choice of means to one's own happiness;
i。e。; the precept of prudence; is still always hypothetical; the
action is not commanded absolutely; but only as means to another
purpose。
*The word prudence is taken in two senses: in the one it may bear
the name of knowledge of the world; in the other that of private
prudence。 The former is a man's ability to influence others so as to
use them for his own purposes。 The latter is the sagacity to combine
all these purposes for his own lasting benefit。 This latter is
properly that to which the value even of the former is reduced; and
when a man is prudent in the former sense; but not in the latter; we
might better say of him that he is clever and cunning; but; on the
whole; imprudent。
Finally; there is an imperative which commands a certain conduct
immediately; without having as its condition any other purpose to be
attained by it。 This imperative is categorical。 It concerns not the
matter of the action; or its intended result; but its form and the
principle of which it is itself a result; and what is essentially good
in it consists in the mental disposition; let the consequence be
what it may。 This imperative may be called that of morality。
There is a marked distinction also between the volitions on these
three sorts of principles in the dissimilarity of the obligation of
the will。 In order to mark this difference more clearly; I think
they would be most suitably named in their order if we said they are
either rules of skill; or counsels of prudence; or commands (laws)
of morality。 For it is law only that involves the conception of an
unconditional and objective necessity; which is consequently
universally valid; and commands are laws which must be obeyed; that
is; must be followed; even in opposition to inclination。 Counsels;
indeed; involve necessity; but one which can only hold under a
contingent subjective condition; viz。; they depend on whether this
or that man reckons this or that as part of his happiness; the
categorical imperative; on the contrary; is not limited by any
condition; and as being absolutely; although practically; necessary;
may b
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!